Reason’s function is to embody the good, but the test of excellence is
itself ideal; therefore before we can assure ourselves that reason has
been manifested in any given case we must make out the reasonableness of
the ideal that inspires us. And in general, before we can convince
ourselves that a Life of Reason, or practice guided by science and
directed toward spiritual goods, is at all worth having, we must make out
the possibility and character of its ultimate end. Yet each ideal is its
own justification; so that the only sense in which an ultimate end can be
established and become a test of general progress is this: that a harmony
and co-operation of impulses should be conceived, leading to the maximum
satisfaction possible in the whole community of spirits affected by our
action. Now, without considering for the present any concrete Utopia,
such, for instance, as Plato’s Republic or the heavenly beatitude
described by theologians, we may inquire what formal qualities are imposed
on the ideal by its nature and function and by the relation it bears to
experience and to desire.
The ideal has the same relation to given demands that the reality has to
given perceptions. In the face of the ideal, particular demands forfeit
their authority and the goods to which a particular being may aspire cease
to be absolute; nay, the satisfaction of desire comes to appear an
indifferent or unholy thing when compared or opposed to the ideal to be
realised. So, precisely, in perception, flying impressions come to be
regarded as illusory when contrasted with a stable conception of reality.
Yet of course flying impressions are the only material out of which that
conception can be formed. Life itself is a flying impression, and had we
no personal and instant experience, importuning us at each successive
moment, we should have no occasion to ask for a reality at all, and no
materials out of which to construct so gratuitous an idea. In the same way
present demands are the only materials and occasions for any ideal:
without demands the ideal would have no locus standi or foothold in
the world, no power, no charm, and no prerogative. If the ideal can
confront particular desires and put them to shame, that happens only
because the ideal is the object of a more profound and voluminous desire
and embodies the good which they blindly and perhaps deviously pursue.
Demands could not be misdirected, goods sought could not be false, if the
standard by which they are to be corrected were not constructed out of
them. Otherwise each demand would render its object a detached, absolute,
and unimpeachable good. But when each desire in turn has singed its wings
and retired before some disillusion, reflection may set in to suggest
residual satisfactions that may still be possible, or some shifting of the
ground by which much of what was hoped for may yet be attained.
The force for this new trial is but the old impulse renewed; this new hope
is a justified remnant of the old optimism. Each passion, in this second
campaign, takes the field conscious that it has indomitable enemies and
ready to sign a reasonable peace, and even to capitulate before superior
forces. Such tameness may be at first merely a consequence of exhaustion
and prudence; but a mortal will, though absolute in its deliverances, is
very far from constant, and its sacrifices soon constitute a habit, its
exile a new home. The old ambition, now proved to be unrealisable, begins
to seem capricious and extravagant; the circle of possible satisfactions
becomes the field of conventional happiness. Experience, which brings
about this humbler and more prosaic state of mind, has its own imaginative
fruits. Among those forces which compelled each particular impulse to
abate its pretensions, the most conspicuous were other impulses, other
interests active in oneself and in one’s neighbours. When the power of
these alien demands is recognised they begin, in a physical way, to be
respected; when an adjustment to them is sought they begin to be
understood, for it is only by studying their expression and tendency that
the degree of their hostility can be measured. But to understand is more
than to forgive, it is to adopt; and the passion that thought merely to
withdraw into a sullen and maimed self-indulgence can feel itself expanded
by sympathies which in its primal vehemence it would have excluded
altogether. Experience, in bringing humility, brings intelligence also.
Personal interests begin to seem relative, factors only in a general
voluminous welfare expressed in many common institutions and arts, moulds
for whatever is communicable or rational in every passion. Each original
impulse, when trimmed down more or less according to its degree of
savageness, can then inhabit the state, and every good, when sufficiently
transfigured, can be found again in the general ideal. The factors may
indeed often be unrecognisable in the result, so much does the process of
domestication transform them; but the interests that animated them survive
this discipline and the new purpose is really esteemed; else the ideal
would have no moral force. An ideal representing no living interest would
be irrelevant to practice, just as a conception of reality would be
irrelevant to perception which should not be composed of the materials
that sense supplies, or should not re-embody actual sensations in an
intelligible system.
Here we have, then, one condition which the ideal must fulfil: it must be
a resultant or synthesis of impulses already afoot. An ideal out of
relation to the actual demands of living beings is so far from being an
ideal that it is not even a good. The pursuit of it would be not the acme
but the atrophy of moral endeavour. Mysticism and asceticism run into this
danger, when the intent to be faithful to a supreme good too symbolically
presented breeds a superstitious repugnance toward everything naturally
prized. So also an artificial scepticism can regard all experience as
deceptive, by contrasting it with the chimera of an absolute reality. As
an absolute reality would be indescribable and without a function in the
elucidation of phenomena, so a supreme good which was good for nobody
would be without conceivable value. Respect for such an idol is a
dialectical superstition; and if zeal for that shibboleth should actually
begin to inhibit the exercise of intelligent choice or the development of
appreciation for natural pleasures, it would constitute a reversal of the
Life of Reason which, if persistently indulged in, could only issue in
madness or revert to imbecility.
No less important, however, than this basis which the ideal must have in
extant demands, is the harmony with which reason must endow it. If without
the one the ideal loses its value, without the other it loses its
finality. Human nature is fluid and imperfect; its demands are expressed
in incidental desires, elicited by a variety of objects which perhaps
cannot coexist in the world. If we merely transcribe these miscellaneous
demands or allow these floating desires to dictate to us the elements of
the ideal, we shall never come to a Whole or to an End. One new fancy
after another will seem an embodiment of perfection, and we shall
contradict each expression of our ideal by every other. A certain school
of philosophy—if we may give that name to the systematic neglect of
reason—has so immersed itself in the contemplation of this sort of
inconstancy, which is indeed prevalent enough in the world, that it has
mistaken it for a normal and necessary process. The greatness of the ideal
has been put in its vagueness and in an elasticity which makes it wholly
indeterminate and inconsistent. The goal of progress, beside being thus
made to lie at every point of the compass in succession, is removed to an
infinite distance, whereby the possibility of attaining it is denied and
progress itself is made illusory. For a progress must be directed to
attaining some definite type of life, the counterpart of a given natural
endowment, and nothing can be called an improvement which does not contain
an appreciable benefit. A victory would be a mockery that left us, for
some new reason, as much impeded as before and as far removed from peace.
The picture of life as an eternal war for illusory ends was drawn at first
by satirists, unhappily with too much justification in the facts. Some
grosser minds, too undisciplined to have ever pursued a good either truly
attainable or truly satisfactory, then proceeded to mistake that satire on
human folly for a sober account of the whole universe; and finally others
were not ashamed to represent it as the ideal itself—so soon is the
dyer’s hand subdued to what it works in. A barbarous mind cannot conceive
life, like health, as a harmony continually preserved or restored, and
containing those natural and ideal activities which disease merely
interrupts. Such a mind, never having tasted order, cannot conceive it,
and identifies progress with new conflicts and life with continual death.
Its deification of unreason, instability, and strife comes partly from
piety and partly from inexperience. There is piety in saluting nature in
her perpetual flux and in thinking that since no equilibrium is maintained
for ever none, perhaps, deserves to be. There is inexperience in not
considering that wherever interests and judgments exist, the natural flux
has fallen, so to speak, into a vortex, and created a natural good, a
cumulative life, and an ideal purpose. Art, science, government, human
nature itself, are self-defining and self-preserving: by partly fixing a
structure they fix an ideal. But the barbarian can hardly regard such
things, for to have distinguished and fostered them would be to have
founded a civilisation.
Reason’s function in defining the ideal is in principle extremely simple,
although all time and all existence would have to be gathered in before
the applications of that principle could be exhausted. A better example of
its essential working could hardly be found than one which Darwin gives to
illustrate the natural origin of moral sense. A swallow, impelled by
migratory instincts to leave a nest full of unfledged young, would endure
a moral conflict. The more lasting impulse, memory being assumed, would
prompt a moral judgment when it emerged again after being momentarily
obscured by an intermittent passion. “While the mother bird is
feeding or brooding over her nestlings, the maternal instinct is probably
stronger than the migratory; but the instinct which is more persistent
gains the victory, and at last, at a moment when her young ones are not in
sight, she takes flight and deserts them. When arrived at the end of her
long journey, and the migratory instinct ceases to act, what an agony of
remorse each bird would feel if, from being endowed with great mental
activity, she could not prevent the image continually passing before her
mind of her young ones perishing in the bleak north from cold and hunger.”[E] She would doubtless
upbraid herself, like any sinner, for a senseless perfidy to her own
dearest good. The perfidy, however, was not wholly senseless, because the
forgotten instinct was not less natural and necessary than the remembered
one, and its satisfaction no less true. Temptation has the same basis as
duty. The difference is one of volume and permanence in the rival
satisfactions, and the attitude conscience will assume toward these
depends more on the representability of the demands compared than on their
original vehemence or ultimate results.
Conscience and reason compared.
A passionate conscience may thus arise in the play of impulses differing
in permanence, without involving a judicial exercise of reason. Nor does
such a conscience involve a synthetic ideal, but only the ideal presence
of particular demands. Conflicts in the conscience are thus quite natural
and would continually occur but for the narrowness that commonly
characterises a mind inspired by passion. A life of sin and repentance is
as remote as possible from a Life of Reason. Yet the same situation which
produces conscience and the sense of duty is an occasion for applying
reason to action and for forming an ideal, so soon as the demands and
satisfactions concerned are synthesised and balanced imaginatively. The
stork might do more than feel the conflict of his two impulses, he might
do more than embody in alternation the eloquence of two hostile thoughts.
He might pass judgment upon them impartially and, in the felt presence of
both, conceive what might be a union or compromise between them.
This resultant object of pursuit, conceived in reflection and in itself
the initial goal of neither impulse, is the ideal of a mind occupied by
the two: it is the aim prescribed by reason under the circumstances. It
differs from the prescription of conscience, in that conscience is often
the spokesman of one interest or of a group of interests in opposition to
other primary impulses which it would annul altogether; while reason and
the ideal are not active forces nor embodiments of passion at all, but
merely a method by which objects of desire are compared in reflection. The
goodness of an end is felt inwardly by conscience; by reason it can be
only taken upon trust and registered as a fact. For conscience the object
of an opposed will is an evil, for reason it is a good on the same ground
as any other good, because it is pursued by a natural impulse and can
bring a real satisfaction. Conscience, in fine, is a party to moral
strife, reason an observer of it who, however, plays the most important
and beneficent part in the outcome by suggesting the terms of peace. This
suggested peace, inspired by sympathy and by knowledge of the world, is
the ideal, which borrows its value and practical force from the irrational
impulses which it embodies, and borrows its final authority from the truth
with which it recognises them all and the necessity by which it imposes on
each such sacrifices as are requisite to a general harmony.
Reason imposes no new sacrifice.
Could each impulse, apart from reason, gain perfect satisfaction, it would
doubtless laugh at justice. The divine, to exercise suasion, must use an
argumentum ad hominem; reason must justify itself to the heart. But
perfect satisfaction is what an irresponsible impulse can never hope for:
all other impulses, though absent perhaps from the mind, are none the less
present in nature and have possession of the field through their physical
basis. They offer effectual resistance to a reckless intruder. To
disregard them is therefore to gain nothing: reason, far from creating the
partial renunciation and proportionate sacrifices which it imposes, really
minimises them by making them voluntary and fruitful. The ideal, which may
seem to wear so severe a frown, really fosters all possible pleasures;
what it retrenches is nothing to what blind forces and natural
catastrophes would otherwise cut off; while it sweetens what it sanctions,
adding to spontaneous enjoyments a sense of moral security and an
intellectual light.
Natural goods attainable and compatible in principle.
Those who are guided only by an irrational conscience can hardly
understand what a good life would be. Their Utopias have to be
supernatural in order that the irresponsible rules which they call
morality may lead by miracle to happy results. But such a magical and
undeserved happiness, if it were possible, would be unsavoury: only one
phase of human nature would be satisfied by it, and so impoverished an
ideal cannot really attract the will. For human nature has been moulded by
the same natural forces among which its ideal has to be fulfilled, and,
apart from a certain margin of wild hopes and extravagances, the things
man’s heart desires are attainable under his natural conditions and would
not be attainable elsewhere. The conflict of desires and interests in the
world is not radical any more than man’s dissatisfaction with his own
nature can be; for every particular ideal, being an expression of human
nature in operation, must in the end involve the primary human faculties
and cannot be essentially incompatible with any other ideal which involves
them too.
To adjust all demands to one ideal and adjust that ideal to its natural
conditions—in other words, to live the Life of Reason—is
something perfectly possible; for those demands, being akin to one another
in spite of themselves, can be better furthered by co-operation than by
blind conflict, while the ideal, far from demanding any profound
revolution in nature, merely expresses her actual tendency and forecasts
what her perfect functioning would be.
Harmony the formal and intrinsic demand of reason.
Reason as such represents or rather constitutes a single formal interest,
the interest in harmony. When two interests are simultaneous and fall
within one act of apprehension the desirability of harmonising them is
involved in the very effort to realise them together. If attention and
imagination are steady enough to face this implication and not to allow
impulse to oscillate between irreconcilable tendencies, reason comes into
being. Henceforth things actual and things desired are confronted by an
ideal which has both pertinence and authority.
FOOTNOTES:
[E] Descent of
Man, chapter iii.