Chance, Love, And Logic: Philosophical Essays
Charles S. (Charles Sanders) Peirce
20 chapters
8 hour read
Selected Chapters
20 chapters
Chance, Love, and Logic
Chance, Love, and Logic
International Library of Psychology Philosophy and Scientific Method General Editor : C. K. Ogden, m.a. VOLUMES ALREADY PUBLISHED PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES, by G. E. Moore , Litt.D. THE MISUSE OF MIND, by Karin Stephen . Prefatory note by Henri Bergson CONFLICT AND DREAM, by W. H. R. Rivers , F.R.S. PSYCHOLOGY AND POLITICS, by W. H. R. Rivers , F.R.S. TRACTATUS LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS, by L. Wittgenstein . Introduction by Bertrand Russell THE MEASUREMENT OF EMOTION, by W. Whately Smith . Introduction b
2 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
PREFACE
PREFACE
In the essays gathered together in this volume we have the most developed and coherent available account of the philosophy of Charles S. Peirce, whom James, Royce, Dewey, and leading thinkers in England, France, Germany and Italy have placed in the forefront of the great seminal minds of recent times. Besides their inherent value as the expression of a highly original and fruitful mind, unusually well trained and informed in the exact sciences, these essays are also important as giving us the so
4 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
I
I
Peirce was by antecedents, training, and occupation a scientist. He was a son of Benjamin Peirce, the great Harvard mathematician, and his early environment, together with his training in the Lawrence Scientific School, justified his favorite claim that he was brought up in a laboratory. He made important contributions not only in mathematical logic but also in photometric astronomy, geodesy, and psychophysics, as well as in philology. For many years Peirce worked on the problems of geodesy, and
10 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
II
II
This insistence on the continuity so effectually used as a heuristic principle in natural and mathematical science, distinguishes the pragmatism of Peirce from that of his follower James. Prof. Dewey has developed this point authoritatively in the supplementary essay; but in view of the general ignorance as to the sources of pragmatism which prevails in this incurious age, some remarks on the actual historical origin of pragmatism may be in order. There can be little doubt that Peirce was led to
3 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
III
III
Peirce preferred to call himself a logician, and his contributions to logic have so far proved his most generally recognized achievement. For a right perspective of these contributions we may well begin with the observation that though few branches of philosophy have been cultivated as continuously as logic, Kant was able to affirm that the science of logic had made no substantial progress since the time of Aristotle. The reason for this is that Aristotle’s logic, the logic of classes, was based
9 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
IV
IV
Not only the pragmatism and the radical empiricism of James, but the idealism of Royce and the more recent movement of neo-realism are largely indebted to Peirce. It may seem strange that the same thinker should be claimed as foster-father of both recent idealism and realism, and some may take it as another sign of his lack of consistency. But this seeming strangeness is really due to the looseness with which the antithesis between realism and idealism has generally been put. If by idealism we d
4 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
PROEM THE RULES OF PHILOSOPHY[25]
PROEM THE RULES OF PHILOSOPHY[25]
Descartes is the father of modern philosophy, and the spirit of Cartesianism—that which principally distinguishes it from the scholasticism which it displaced—may be compendiously stated as follows: 1. It teaches that philosophy must begin with universal doubt; whereas scholasticism had never questioned fundamentals. 2. It teaches that the ultimate test of certainty is to be found in the individual consciousness; whereas scholasticism had rested on the testimony of sages and of the Catholic Chur
3 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
CHANCE AND LOGIC FIRST PAPER THE FIXATION OF BELIEF[26]
CHANCE AND LOGIC FIRST PAPER THE FIXATION OF BELIEF[26]
Few persons care to study logic, because everybody conceives himself to be proficient enough in the art of reasoning already. But I observe that this satisfaction is limited to one’s own ratiocination, and does not extend to that of other men. We come to the full possession of our power of drawing inferences the last of all our faculties, for it is not so much a natural gift as a long and difficult art. The history of its practice would make a grand subject for a book. The medieval schoolman, fo
32 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
SECOND PAPER HOW TO MAKE OUR IDEAS CLEAR[31]
SECOND PAPER HOW TO MAKE OUR IDEAS CLEAR[31]
Whoever has looked into a modern treatise on logic of the common sort, will doubtless remember the two distinctions between clear and obscure conceptions, and between distinct and confused conceptions. They have lain in the books now for nigh two centuries, unimproved and unmodified, and are generally reckoned by logicians as among the gems of their doctrine. A clear idea is defined as one which is so apprehended that it will be recognized wherever it is met with, and so that no other will be mi
37 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
THIRD PAPER THE DOCTRINE OF CHANCES[34]
THIRD PAPER THE DOCTRINE OF CHANCES[34]
It is a common observation that a science first begins to be exact when it is quantitatively treated. What are called the exact sciences are no others than the mathematical ones. Chemists reasoned vaguely until Lavoisier showed them how to apply the balance to the verification of their theories, when chemistry leaped suddenly into the position of the most perfect of the classificatory sciences. It has thus become so precise and certain that we usually think of it along with optics, thermotics, a
28 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
FOURTH PAPER THE PROBABILITY OF INDUCTION[40]
FOURTH PAPER THE PROBABILITY OF INDUCTION[40]
We have found that every argument derives its force from the general truth of the class of inferences to which it belongs; and that probability is the proportion of arguments carrying truth with them among those of any genus . This is most conveniently expressed in the nomenclature of the medieval logicians. They called the fact expressed by a premise an antecedent , and that which follows from it its consequent ; while the leading principle, that every (or almost every) such antecedent is follo
33 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
FIFTH PAPER THE ORDER OF NATURE[44]
FIFTH PAPER THE ORDER OF NATURE[44]
Any proposition whatever concerning the order of Nature must touch more or less upon religion. In our day, belief, even in these matters, depends more and more upon the observation of facts. If a remarkable and universal orderliness be found in the universe, there must be some cause for this regularity, and science has to consider what hypotheses might account for the phenomenon. One way of accounting for it, certainly, would be to suppose that the world is ordered by a superior power. But if th
32 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
SIXTH PAPER DEDUCTION, INDUCTION, AND HYPOTHESIS[51]
SIXTH PAPER DEDUCTION, INDUCTION, AND HYPOTHESIS[51]
The chief business of the logician is to classify arguments; for all testing clearly depends on classification. The classes of the logicians are defined by certain typical forms called syllogisms. For example, the syllogism called Barbara is as follows: Or, to put words for letters— The “is P” of the logicians stands for any verb, active or neuter. It is capable of strict proof (with which, however, I will not trouble the reader) that all arguments whatever can be put into this form; but only un
8 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
I. THE ARCHITECTURE OF THEORIES[54]
I. THE ARCHITECTURE OF THEORIES[54]
Of the fifty or hundred systems of philosophy that have been advanced at different times of the world’s history, perhaps the larger number have been, not so much results of historical evolution, as happy thoughts which have accidently occurred to their authors. An idea which has been found interesting and fruitful has been adopted, developed, and forced to yield explanations of all sorts of phenomena. The English have been particularly given to this way of philosophizing; witness, Hobbes, Hartle
26 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
II. THE DOCTRINE OF NECESSITY EXAMINED[59]
II. THE DOCTRINE OF NECESSITY EXAMINED[59]
In The Monist for January, 1891, I endeavored to show what elementary ideas ought to enter into our view of the universe. I may mention that on those considerations I had already grounded a cosmical theory, and from it had deduced a considerable number of consequences capable of being compared with experience. This comparison is now in progress, but under existing circumstances must occupy many years. I propose here to examine the common belief that every single fact in the universe is precisely
29 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
III. THE LAW OF MIND[61]
III. THE LAW OF MIND[61]
In an article published in The Monist for January, 1891, I endeavored to show what ideas ought to form the warp of a system of philosophy, and particularly emphasized that of absolute chance. In the number of April, 1892, I argued further in favor of that way of thinking, which it will be convenient to christen tychism (from τύχη, chance). A serious student of philosophy will be in no haste to accept or reject this doctrine; but he will see in it one of the chief attitudes which speculative thou
47 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
IV. MAN’S GLASSY ESSENCE[63]
IV. MAN’S GLASSY ESSENCE[63]
In The Monist for January, 1891, I tried to show what conceptions ought to form the brick and mortar of a philosophical system. Chief among these was that of absolute chance for which I argued again in last April’s number. [64] In July, I applied another fundamental idea, that of continuity, to the law of mind. Next in order, I have to elucidate, from the point of view chosen, the relation between the psychical and physical aspects of a substance. The first step towards this ought, I think, to b
36 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
V. EVOLUTIONARY LOVE[72] AT FIRST BLUSH. COUNTER-GOSPELS
V. EVOLUTIONARY LOVE[72] AT FIRST BLUSH. COUNTER-GOSPELS
Philosophy, when just escaping from its golden pupa-skin, mythology, proclaimed the great evolutionary agency of the universe to be Love. Or, since this pirate-lingo, English, is poor in such-like words, let us say Eros, the exuberance-love. Afterwards, Empedocles set up passionate-love and hate as the two co-ordinate powers of the universe. In some passages, kindness is the word. But certainly, in any sense in which it has an opposite, to be senior partner of that opposite, is the highest posit
37 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
Supplementary Essay THE PRAGMATISM OF PEIRCE BY John Dewey
Supplementary Essay THE PRAGMATISM OF PEIRCE BY John Dewey
The term pragmatism was introduced into literature in the opening sentences of Professor James’s California Union address in 1898. The sentences run as follows: “The principle of pragmatism, as we may call it, may be expressed in a variety of ways, all of them very simple. In the Popular Science Monthly for January, 1878, Mr. Charles S. Peirce introduces it as follows:” etc. The readers who have turned to the volume referred to have not, however, found the word there. From other sources we know
12 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter
BIBLIOGRAPHY OF PEIRCE’S PUBLISHED WRITINGS
BIBLIOGRAPHY OF PEIRCE’S PUBLISHED WRITINGS
I. Writings of General Interest. [88] A. Three papers in the Journal of Speculative Philosophy , Vol. 2 (1868). 1. “Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man,” pp. 103-114. 2. “Some Consequences of Four Incapacities,” pp. 140-157. 3. “Ground of Validity of the Laws of Logic,” pp. 193-208. These three papers, somewhat loosely connected, deal mainly with the philosophy of discursive thought. The first deals with our power of intuition, and holds that “every thought is a sign.” The sec
22 minute read
Read Chapter
Read Chapter